Notes â Continued (2 of 2)
6. An Organology of Wars
1. Bergsonâs The Meaning of the War was published in English in 1915; the French text is available at: http://14-18.institut-de-france.fr/1914-discours-henri-bergson.php; English translation is also available on Project Gutenberg: https://www.gutenberg.org/files/17111/17111-h/17111-h.htm.
2. See Die Bibliothek Carl Schmitt, edited by the Carl-Schmitt-Gesellschaft, https://www.carl-schmitt.de/forschung/privatbibliothek-carl-schmitts/.
3. Canguilhem, âMachine and Organism,â in The Knowledge of Life; In Recursivity and Contingency, I tried to reconstruct Bergsonâs general organology through a reading of Creative Evolution and Canguilhemâs commentary on Part III of Bergsonâs Creative Evolution; this chapter constitutes the further interrogation of this subject.
4. Bergson, The Meaning of the War, 34.
5. Bergson, The Two Sources, 268.
6. Marinetti, âThe Futurist Manifesto (1909),â https://www.arthistoryproject.com/artists/filippo-tommaso-marinetti/the-futurist-manifesto/.
7. Bergson, The Meaning of the War, 36.
8. Kapp, Der konstituierte Despotismus und die konstitutionelle Freiheit, 85.
9. See Kawakami and Takeuchi (ed), Overcoming Modernity (èżä»Łăźè¶ ć ); On the discussion of war and the Kyoto School, please see the second part of Hui, The Question Concerning Technology in China.
10. I was made aware by the Russian editor of one of my books, Eugene Kuchinov, that a book published by the nationalist agitator Maxim Kalashnikov was entitled Robot and Cross: Technosense of the Russian Idea.
11. Bergson, The Two Sources, 249.
12. Varela, âSteps to a Cybernetics of Autonomy,â 117.
13. Negri, The End of Sovereignty; see also my discussion in the Introduction.
14. As Charles Taylor said, today Hegelâs ontology of Geist is âclose to incredible,â but at the same time highly relevant, see Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society, 69, 72.
15. Wiener, âSome Moral and Technical Consequences of Automation,â 1358.
16. Wiener, God and Golem, 73
17. Simondon, âCybernĂ©tique et philosophie,â in Sur la Philosophie.
18. Bergson, The Two Sources, 268.
19. Lapoujade, Powers of Time, 81.
20. Bergson, The Two Sources, 265.
21. Bergson, The Two Sources, 263.
22. Lapoujade, Powers of Time, 63: âThe intelligence is precisely what distracts man from life itself; it is a form of inattention to life. The pure intelligence is in effect characterized by a ânatural inability to comprehend lifeâ insofar as it always perceives life from the outside. The intelligence is life having become external to itself.â
23. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, 59â62.
24. Simondon, âCybernĂ©tique et philosophie,â in Sur la Philosophie, 43. Simondon used the term holistic (holique) to describe this form of organization of cybernetics.
25. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, 17.
26. Bergson in The Two Sources proposed what he calls âattachment to lifeâ; however, this attachment to life is not about abandoning technology. Instead, this attachment to life is an act of overcoming. For the discussion between the tension of âattention to lifeâ in his Matter and Memory and âattachment to lifeâ in The Two Sources, please see Lapoujade, Powers of Time, 65â67.
27. On the concept of tragist, see Hui, Art and Cosmotechnics.
28. Schure, Bergson and History, 199.
29. Schure, Bergson and History, 200.
30. It could be equally interesting to compare Bergsonâs interpretation of the external obstacle in evolution and the Hemmung in Schellingâs recursive form of nature.
31. Bergson, Creative Evolution, 47â48.
32. Bergson, The Two Sources, 257.
33. See Miquel, âBergson and Darwin.â
34. Even though Bergson never mentioned the name Hegel, and he rejected any telos of history, one wonders how far this is from Hegelâs own dialectics and the concept of sublation not as cancellation but as reconciliation.
35. Bergson, The Two Sources, 234.
36. Deleuze, Bergsonism, 13.
37. Bergson, The Two Sources, 268. âNe nous bornons donc pas Ă dire, comme nous le faisions plus haut, que la mystique appelle la mĂ©canique. Ajoutons que le corps agrandi attend un supplĂ©ment dâĂąme, et que la mĂ©canique exigerait une mystique. Les origines de cette mĂ©canique sont peut-ĂȘtre plus mystiques quâon ne le croirait; elle ne retrouvera sa direction vraie, elle ne rendra des services proportionnĂ©s Ă sa puissance, que si lâhumanitĂ© quâelle a courbĂ©e encore davantage vers la terre arrive par elle Ă se redresser, et Ă regarder le ciel.â
38. Hawking, âArtificial Intelligence Could Spell the End of the Human Race.â
39. Schure, Bergson and History, 204.
40. Lapoujade, Powers of Time, 66. Lapoujade sees the paradox between delusion (délire) and believing, for delusion can only become vital when it is believed.
41. On the nonrational, see Hui, Art and Cosmotechnics, where we elaborated what we call âepistemology of the unknown.â The nonrational is distinguished from the irrational, because the nonrational is that which remains unknown and unknowable, however essential to the plane of consistence of a spiritual life.
42. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 338â39.
43. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 339.
44. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 95.
45. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 338. âMais la simple observation dâun animal ou dâune technique dĂ©montre que la tendance gĂ©nĂ©rale ne contient pas toutes les caractĂ©ristiques: le sabre, qui rĂ©alise dans tous ses types un ensemble harmonieux, offre pourtant des formes extrĂȘmement nombreuses conditionnes les unes par la matiĂšre, les autres par lâusage particulier de lâarme, les coutumes de lâescrime locale, les traditions esthĂ©tiques, etc.â
46. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 342.
47. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 396. âNous avons fait la part de deux notions qui semblent dominer les faits, parce quâelles fournissent une vue primordiale sur lâĂvolution: la tendance et le milieu extĂ©rieur.â
48. See Hui, The Question Concerning Technology in China.
49. Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et Technique, 344.
50. This leads to the association of modernization and resistance, in the sense that the history of modernization of the non-West is a history of resistance against the West. See Takeuchi, What Is Modernity?.
51. Lefebvre, Le manifeste différentialiste.
52. Benjamin, âThe Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction,â 218.
53. See Ober, Demopolis.
54. Lenin, State and Revolution, 54, italic original; also cited by Lefebvre, State, Space, World, 85.
55. Lenin, State and Revolution, 51.
56. Lenin, State and Revolution, 53â54.
57. Lenin, State and Revolution, 129.
58. Democracy as an act that allows the system to differentiate is a key argument of Niklas Luhmann against the classical concept of democracy, which means eliminating other options, such as choosing between A and B. Luhmann believes that systems theory provides a concept of democracy more appropriate to our time. See Luhmann, âKomplexitĂ€t und Demokratie,â 36.
59. ChĂ©rif, Islam and the West, 43: âDemocracy is always to come, it is a promise, and it is in the name of that promise that one can always criticize, question that which is proposed as the facto democracy. Consequently, I believe that there doesnât exist in the world a democracy suitable for the concept of the democracy to come.â
60. Chérif, Islam and the West, 50.
61. Chérif, Islam and the West, 44.
62. However, to be noted is that Derridaâs democracy to come is neither a Kantian idea such as the world republic of Karatani nor is it a messianic politics like that of Walter Benjamin. See Derrida, âThe Force of Law,â 965: commenting on the idea of justice, Derrida said, âI would hesitate to assimilate too quickly this âidea of justiceâ to a regulative idea (in the Kantian sense), to a messianic promise or to other horizons of the same typeâ (italics in original).
63. See Gille, Histoire des techniques.
64. Hui, âFor a Planetary Thinking.â
65. Wilson, Biophilia, 11.
66. Wilson, Biophilia, 71.
67. Wilson, Half-Earth, Prologue.
68. Wilson, Biophilia, 138.
69. Shiva, âMonocultures of the Mind,â 237â48.
70. GĂŒnther Anders made an interesting remark when he said that even if one stops experimenting on the atomic bomb, and destroys all the existing bombs physically, the risk of the atomic catastrophe still exists; see Anders, âCommandments in the Atomic Age, 1957.â
71. Hui, âMachine and Ecology.â
72. Mumford, The Myth of the Machine. Vol. 2., 271; Mumford reflects on the American megamachine after the Second World War.
7. Toward an Epistemological Diplomacy
1. Marx, Capital, 492.
2. Arendt, The Human Condition, 127.
3. This is the subject of Hui, Art and Cosmotechnics.
4. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects.
5. Sohn-Rethel, âDas Ideal des Kaputten: Ăber neapolitanische Technik,â 41â48; the English translation by John Garvey, âThe Ideal of the Broken Down,â is available at https://hardcrackers.com/ideal-broken-neapolitan-approach-things-technical/.
6. Sohn-Rethel, âThe Ideal of the Broken Down.â
7. For a discussion on Sohn-Rethel and Simondon on the question of technical knowledge, see Hui, âNotes on Technical Normativity.â
8. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, 176â77.
9. Hui, âApropos Technophany.â
10. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, 234.
11. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, 49.
12. Simondon, On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, 49.
13. Hazard, The Crisis of the European Mind, 20.
14. KojĂšve, Kant, 70; KojĂšve argues in the book that Kantâs Critique of Judgment marks a turn from the discursive mode of truth to the mode of âas ifâ by eliminating the thing-in-itself; by doing so, KojĂšve also claims that the Kantian system is transformed quasi-automatically into a Hegelian system of knowledge (103).
15. Achilles Skordas defines these sets of conflicts as that which characterizes a neo-Hobbesian age; see Skordas, âThe Rise of the Neo-Hobbesian Age.â
16. GachĂ©, âForeword,â xiii.
17. Macron, âLâautonomie stratĂ©gique.â A similar proposal was made by Habermas in 2003, arguing that Europe should maintain distance from the unilateral policy of the United States; see Habermas and Derrida, âFebruary 15, or What Binds Europeans Together.â
18. Cacciari, The Withholding Power, 110. This reading of Epimetheus seems almost opposite to Schmittâs; see discussion in chapter 5.
19. Cacciari, The Withholding Power, 114.
20. Cacciari, The Withholding Power, 118.
21. Elpis, meaning hope or expectation, according to Hesiodâs Works and Days, is the last object in Pandoraâs box. As expectation, it is also a form of anticipation, and in this sense, it complicates Cacciariâs metaphorical and oppositional play of the collapse of the Promethean foresight and the replacement by the Epimethean calculation.
22. In the history of philosophy, the philosophical epistÄme and the sophistic technÄ were opposed, and technÄ was devaluated in face of epistÄme. Since the Second Industrial Revolution, we observe a transformation of the relation between them, that they have been integrated through the idea of constant innovation. See Stiegler, Technics and Time, Vol. 1, 1, 40â43.
23. For an elaboration on the individuation of thinking, see Hui, Post-Europe (forthcoming 2024)
24. Glissant, âCreolization in the Making of the Americas,â 82.
25. Glissant, Poetics of Relation, 108.
26. Simondonâs anthropological analysis of the genesis of technicity in the third part of On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects was influenced by James Fraser, Bergson, Leroi-Gourhan, and others.
27. Simondon, âPsychosociologie de la technicitĂ©,â in Sur la Technique, 33.
28. See Hui and Halpin, âCollective Individuation,â 103â16, for an analysis of the history of social networks, its ontological and epistemological assumptions.
29. Gerovitch, âArtificial Intelligence with a National Face.â
30. See Hui, Cybernetics for the 21st Century Vol. 1, which aims at an epistemological reconstruction of cybernetics in the twentieth century across various regions, including the United States, Soviet Union, Poland, France, China, Japan, and Latin American countries.
31. Santos, Epistemologies of the South.
32. LĂ©vi-Strauss in Tristes Tropiques coined the term âentropology,â which suggests renaming his own discipline of anthropology. Entropology describes the disintegration of cultures under assault from Western expansion. See LĂ©vi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, 414: âAnthropology could with advantage be changed into âentropology,â as the name of the discipline concerned with the study of the highest manifestations of this process of disintegration.â For the question of entropy and ecology, also see White, âOutline to an Architectonics of Thermodynamics.â
33. Kant, âIdea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Aim,â in Political Writings, 45.
34. Zammito, The Genesis of Kantâs Critique of Judgment, 328.
35. Kant, âPerpetual Peace,â in Political Writings, 107â8. Italics in original.
36. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A833, B861.
37. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A832 B860.
38. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A646â47, B674â75.
39. Rajiva, âIs Hypothetical Reason a Precursor to Reflective Judgment?â
40. Kant, Critique of Judgment (KU 438, 305), cited by Ypi, The Architectonic of Reason, 117: âThere actually lies in us a priori an idea of a highest being, resting on a very different use of reason (its practical use), which drives us to amplify physical teleologyâs defective representation of the original ground of the ends of nature into the concept of a deity.â
41. Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, 168.
42. Karatani, The Structure of World History, 232.
43. Karatani, The Structure of World History, 233.
44. Mann and Wainwright, Climate Leviathan.
45. Karatani, The Structure of World History, 283â84. Karataniâs optimism is based on a set of seemingly mistaken observations, which he states further on the next page: âThe growth of industrial capitalism required three preconditions: first, that nature supply unlimited resources from outside the industrial structure; second, that human nature be available in an unlimited supply outside the capitalist economy; and, third, that technological innovation continue without limit. These three conditions have been rapidly disappearing since 1990.â
46. Nakhimovsky, The Closed Commercial State, 80.
47. Fichte, The Closed Commercial State, 145; also quoted by Nakhimovsky, The Closed Commercial State, 77. (Here I used the official translation published by SUNY Press.)
48. Fichte, The Closed Commercial State, 198â99.
49. The launch of Huaweiâs Mate 60 Pro in September 2023 has created polar responses: on the one hand, the national pride of Chinese citizens who celebrated the breakthrough against the U.S. sanction on microchips; on the other hand, an even more fierce restriction might be imposed on Chinese firms from the U.S. side to weaken Chinaâs capacity of producing 7 nanometer microchips on a large scale.
50. Henry Kissinger, âHow the Enlightenment Endsâ: âThe Enlightenment started with essentially philosophical insights spread by a new technology. Our period is moving in the opposite direction. It has generated a potentially dominating technology in search of a guiding philosophy.â
51. There are many wonderful works on the intellectual history of the Enlightenment and its plead for nonpartisan reason. One of the outstanding works on this account is Koselleck, Critique and Crisis, especially chapter 8, âThe Process of Criticism (Schiller, Simon, Bayle, Voltaire, Diderot and the EncyclopĂ©die, Kant).â
52. Zammito suggests an âethical turnâ in Kantâs Critique of Judgment, as he writes that âKant is really concerned with the kind of world which would exist were everyone to be fully moral. In a world of full worthiness, everyone should also be proportionately happy. What is required to compel the natural order to make happiness for man as a species a real possibility is nothing less than God.â Zammito, The Genesis of Kantâs Critique of Judgment, 339. We know that the pursuit of the systematic unity of reason has its main aim (Hauptzwecke) in what Kant called a general happiness (allgemeine GlĂŒckseligkeit), which ended his section on âThe Architectonic of Pure Reasonâ in the Critique of Pure Reason, A851 B879. The possibility of general happiness is taken up as the âhighest goodâ in the Critique of Practical Reason, a moral world in which actions are guided by moral laws defined according to the categorical imperative, and happiness is proportional to virtue.