Skip to main content

The Affect Lab: NOTES

The Affect Lab
NOTES
    • Notifications
    • Privacy
  • Project HomeThe Affect Lab
  • Projects
  • Learn more about Manifold

Notes

Show the following:

  • Annotations
  • Resources
Search within:

Adjust appearance:

  • font
    Font style
  • color scheme
  • Margins
table of contents
  1. Cover
  2. Title Page
  3. Copyright
  4. Contents
  5. Introduction: Techniques of the Affect Lab
  6. 1. William James’s Planchette
  7. 2. Books of Faces
  8. 3. The Prison Dynograph
  9. 4. E-Meter Metaphysics
  10. Conclusion: The Epistemology and Aesthetics of Empathy
  11. Acknowledgments
  12. Notes
  13. Bibliography
  14. Index
  15. Figure Descriptions
  16. About the Author

NOTES

Introduction

  1. 1.Foucault, Birth of the Clinic, 107.

    Return to note reference.

  2. 2.Scarry, Body in Pain, 3.

    Return to note reference.

  3. 3.Kittler, Gramophone, Film, Typewriter, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  4. 4.Wershler, Emerson, and Parikka, Lab Book, 37.

    Return to note reference.

  5. 5.My use of “origin” here follows Foucault, Aesthetics, 369–92.

    Return to note reference.

  6. 6.Cf. Feyerabend, Against Method.

    Return to note reference.

  7. 7.Hemmings, “Invoking Affect”; see also Yao, Disaffected, 9–10.

    Return to note reference.

  8. 8.The distinction made in psychology is, in actuality, far more complex than this, with many different kinds of “feelings” and “emotions” that account for a range of distinct bodily and interpretive states. See Wetherell, Affect and Emotion, 28–31, 59.

    Return to note reference.

  9. 9.Kittler, Gramophone, Film, Typewriter, xl.

    Return to note reference.

  10. 10.See Clough, User Unconscious; Hansen, Feed-Forward; and Sampson, A Sleepwalker’s Guide, among others.

    Return to note reference.

  11. 11.Karppi, Disconnect, 21.

    Return to note reference.

  12. 12.Illouz, Saving the Modern Soul, 86; Liu, Laws of Cool, 89–104.

    Return to note reference.

  13. 13.Lazzarato, “Immaterial Labor”; Illouz, Cold Intimacies.

    Return to note reference.

  14. 14.Han, Burnout Society; Berardi, Soul at Work; Fisher, Capitalist Realism, 21–29.

    Return to note reference.

  15. 15.Ahmed, Promise of Happiness; Davies, Happiness Industry.

    Return to note reference.

  16. 16.Naveh, “Techniques for Emotion Detection,” 3.

    Return to note reference.

  17. 17.Naveh, 4.

    Return to note reference.

  18. 18.Picard, Affective Computing.

    Return to note reference.

  19. 19.Feng, Rosenberg, and Shapiro, “Just-In-Time”; Laine et al., “Production-Level.”

    Return to note reference.

  20. 20.Andrejevic, Infoglut.

    Return to note reference.

  21. 21.Clough, User Unconscious; Hansen, Feed-Forward.

    Return to note reference.

  22. 22.Cf. Serpell, Stranger Faces, 14–15; Leys, “How Did Fear?”

    Return to note reference.

  23. 23.Gates, Our Biometric Future; Magnet, When Biometrics Fail.

    Return to note reference.

  24. 24.On the history of physiognomy, see Pearl, About Faces. On the contemporary role of metrics, see Beer, Metric Power.

    Return to note reference.

  25. 25.Apprich et al., Pattern Discrimination; Noble, Algorithms of Oppression.

    Return to note reference.

  26. 26.Lavater, Essays on Physiognomy, 15.

    Return to note reference.

  27. 27.Lavater, 66.

    Return to note reference.

  28. 28.Lavater, 188.

    Return to note reference.

  29. 29.See Todorov, Face Value; Bunn, Truth Machine; and Sekula, “The Body and the Archive,” among others.

    Return to note reference.

  30. 30.As an example of this, see Safra et al., “Tracking Historical Changes.”

    Return to note reference.

  31. 31.Daston and Galison, Objectivity, 123.

    Return to note reference.

  32. 32.Daston and Galison, 121.

    Return to note reference.

  33. 33.Coon, “Testing the Limits.”

    Return to note reference.

  34. 34.Hookway, “Making of the Experimental Subject.”

    Return to note reference.

  35. 35.Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 204.

    Return to note reference.

  36. 36.Taussig, Defacement, 224.

    Return to note reference.

  37. 37.Bollmer, “Mimetic Sameness”; Chun, “Queering Homophily”; Han, Transparency Society.

    Return to note reference.

  38. 38.Moors, “Theories of Emotion Causation,” 645.

    Return to note reference.

  39. 39.For an outline of FACS in research, see Ekman and Friesen, Facial Action Coding System. For an overview of FACS in the history of emotion detection technology, see Gates, Our Biometric Future, 151–90. For a critique of the development of FACS, see Leys, Ascent of Affect.

    Return to note reference.

  40. 40.Izard, Face of Emotion; Panksepp, Affective Neuroscience.

    Return to note reference.

  41. 41.For instance, see Turner and Stets, Sociology of Emotions, 3; Richardson, “Facial Expression Theory,” 66; and Grodal, Embodied Visions, 18.

    Return to note reference.

  42. 42.What theory knows today is quite different from what it knew when Sedgwick and Frank provoked with their “Shame in the Cybernetic Fold.” See Sedgwick, Touching Feeling, 93–94.

    Return to note reference.

  43. 43.See Leys, Ascent of Affect, 93–119.

    Return to note reference.

  44. 44.Cf. Tagg, Burden of Representation, 4.

    Return to note reference.

  45. 45.See Genosko, Critical Semiotics; Lazzarato, Signs and Machines.

    Return to note reference.

  46. 46.Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway, 46–49; Bollmer, Materialist Media Theory, 46–49.

    Return to note reference.

  47. 47.See Coon, “Standardizing the Subject” and “Testing the Limits.”

    Return to note reference.

  48. 48.Hacking, Representing and Intervening.

    Return to note reference.

  49. 49.As Feyerabend claims, “The material which a scientist actually has at his disposal, his laws, his experimental results, his mathematical techniques, his epistemological prejudices, his attitude towards the absurd consequences of the theories which he accepts, is indeterminate in many ways, ambiguous, and never fully separated from the historical background” (Against Method, 45–46). I generally follow Wershler, Emerson, and Parikka’s heuristic for describing this “material” that is actually available outlined in The Lab Book. Their “extended lab model” argues that labs are comprised of bounded spaces; specific technical apparatuses; an infrastructure which comes from how a lab is funded; people who exist and work in a lab and occupy particular forms of subjectivity; the imaginary, or ideological or discursive frames that cannot be completely reduced to the material reality of a lab; and technique, or practices of the lab. Wershler, Emerson, and Parikka argue that these are all essential, and intertwining, categories for understanding the “situated” practices of laboratories. While I do not emphasize these categories in each chapter by name, and my emphasis almost always begins with either apparatus or technique, I follow their general argument in how I understand a “lab” throughout this book.

    Return to note reference.

  50. 50.As Hans-Jörg Rheinberger notes, epistemology for the authors in this tradition —Gaston Bachelard, Georges Canguilhem, Michel Foucault, and François Delaporte, among others—means “reflecting on the historical conditions under which, and the means with which, things are made into objects of knowledge” (On Historicizing Epistemology, 2).

    Return to note reference.

  51. 51.Bachelard, New Scientific Spirit, 13.

    Return to note reference.

  52. 52.The approach of this book resonates with several other recent works, though it focuses on a different set of technologies and problems than previously covered. This includes Jimena Canales’s Tenth of a Second, Robert Brain’s Pulse of Modernism, and the essays of Otniel E. Dror, such as “The Scientific Image of Emotion” and “Counting the Affects.” Brenton Malin’s Feeling Mediated covers a broader range of technologies than these other writers, but argues that a belief in “media physicalism,” or the capacities of media to physically inscribe and reveal the emotions, is misguided, an argument this book opposes. Branden Hookway’s “Making of the Experimental Subject,” like this book, draws explicit links among the history of psychology, art, and contemporary media.

    Return to note reference.

  53. 53.Galison, Image and Logic, xix.

    Return to note reference.

  54. 54.See, for instance, Frank and Wilson, Silvan Tomkins Handbook, 7. This argument is itself questionable since it presumes language to be disembodied. See Leys, Ascent of Affect.

    Return to note reference.

  55. 55.Silva, Toward a Global Idea of Race.

    Return to note reference.

  56. 56.Ngai, Ugly Feelings, 91; Chen, Animacies, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  57. 57.Schuller, Biopolitics of Feeling; Fretwell, Sensory Experiments.

    Return to note reference.

  58. 58.Yao, Disaffected, 10–11; Ahmed, Cultural Politics of Emotion and Promise of Happiness; Berlant, Female Complaint.

    Return to note reference.

  59. 59.Edelman, No Future.

    Return to note reference.

  60. 60.Fretwell, Sensory Experiments, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  61. 61.This would mean, then, that an affect theory that intends to be antiracist or decolonial has to contend with arguments from media studies such as those offered in Armond Towns’s On Black Media Philosophy.

    Return to note reference.

  62. 62.See Bollmer, “Pathologies of Affect.”

    Return to note reference.

  63. 63.Baron-Cohen, Science of Evil; cf. Rose and Abi-Rached, Neuro, 141–98.

    Return to note reference.

  64. 64.See Chytry, Aesthetic State.

    Return to note reference.

  65. 65.See Ahmed, Cultural Politics of Emotion, 42–61.

    Return to note reference.

  66. 66.This “problem” was perhaps best “solved” in the Gesamtkunstwerk of Richard Wagner, which provides the archetypal cultural technique to produce national bonding through feeling. For an outstanding study (albeit one sympathetic to Wagner) that links Wagnerian theater with this “problem,” along with attempts to theorize Einfühlung, see Koss, Modernism after Wagner. See also Smith, Total Work of Art.

    Return to note reference.

  67. 67.Kant, Practical Philosophy, 17.

    Return to note reference.

  68. 68.Also see Foucault, Ethics, 303–8.

    Return to note reference.

  69. 69.Schiller, Aesthetic Education of Man, 167.

    Return to note reference.

  70. 70.Cf. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment.

    Return to note reference.

  71. 71.Lessing, Hamburg Dramaturgy, 40. See also Baldyga, “‘We Have Actors,’” 14.

    Return to note reference.

  72. 72.Lessing, Hamburg Dramaturgy, 43.

    Return to note reference.

  73. 73.Lavater’s essays were first published a decade after Lessing’s hiring by the theatre. This similarity suggests that Lavater could be framed as responding to the same problem posed by Kant and Schiller—how to employ the aesthetic as a means of producing and judging commonalities assumed essential for national belonging.

    Return to note reference.

  74. 74.Lessing, Hamburg Dramaturgy, 43.

    Return to note reference.

  75. 75.Baldyga, “‘We Have Actors,’” 19.

    Return to note reference.

  76. 76.See Aristotle, Poetics.

    Return to note reference.

  77. 77.Pinotti, “Empathy,” 93.

    Return to note reference.

  78. 78.Cited in Koss, Modernism after Wagner, 68. For a collection of writings of Vischer and others involved in the initial theorization of Einfühlung, see Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form, and Space. See also Jarzombek, Psychologizing of Modernity, 37–72.

    Return to note reference.

  79. 79.Fritz Breithaupt is correct to note that exclusion, partisanship, and factionalism all can be considered linked with the cognitive capacity of empathy. See The Dark Sides of Empathy, 75–130. Philosopher Kate Manne, in her analysis of misogyny, makes a similar move when she frames particular forms of gender-based identification and exclusion as “himpathy.” See Down Girl, 196–205.

    Return to note reference.

  80. 80.“Empathy” can be found in print in English prior to Titchener’s use of the term—in E. L. Hinman’s “Ueber psychophysische Energie,” a brief review of a German article on psychophysics written by German science fiction author Kurd Laßwitz. From the review, it’s unclear what word Laßwitz used in his own writing, but Hinman uses empathy to describe a quantification of neurological energy that correlates to pleasure or pain—a definition that has little to no relation to its use since Titchener’s lectures. Other uses of empathy in English from the early 1900s all appear to refer to Titchener’s translation of Einfühlung.

    Return to note reference.

  81. 81.Depew, “Empathy, Psychology, and Aesthetics,” 99–107; Jahoda, “Theodor Lipps,” 151–63.

    Return to note reference.

  82. 82.Overviews that situate present understandings of empathy in relation to its history include Lanzoni, Empathy ; and Pinotti, L’empathie.

    Return to note reference.

  83. 83.Titchener, Lectures, 21–22.

    Return to note reference.

  84. 84.See Parisi, Archaeologies of Touch, 34–36.

    Return to note reference.

  85. 85.Paterson, How We Became Sensorimotor, 128–29.

    Return to note reference.

  86. 86.Paterson, 127.

    Return to note reference.

  87. 87.Titchener, Lectures, 185 (emphasis added).

    Return to note reference.

  88. 88.James, Principles of Psychology, 1:245–46. Cf. James, Writings, 1902–1910, 1161.

    Return to note reference.

  89. 89.Titchener, Lectures, 188.

    Return to note reference.

  90. 90.This is a similar definition of empathy to the one recently given by art historian David Freedberg and neuroscientist Vittorio Gallese: “Viewers often experience a sense of bodily involvement with the movements that are implied by the physical traces—in brushmarks or paint drippings—of the creative actions of the producer of the work” (“Motion, Emotion and Empathy,” 197). Freedberg and Gallese argue that the pleasure a viewer gets from a painting by Jackson Pollock or Lucio Fontana emerges from the indexicality of motion captured in a work, be it the splattering of paint for the former or the slashing of the canvas for the latter. When looking at a work of Fontana’s, they suggest, “sight of the slashed painting invites a sense of empathetic movement that seems to coincide with the gesture felt to have produced the tear” (197). Empathy, here, is a mental simulation of motion that comes from an inner mirroring of external perception. This would be very similar to Riegl’s sense of haptic vision and how I’m associating it with empathy. This also would suggest that painting—and the physical presence assumed left by the indexical trace of paint—is a cultural technique that precedes our understanding of empathy today.

    Return to note reference.

  91. 91.Titchener, Lectures, 90.

    Return to note reference.

  92. 92.Titchener, 91.

    Return to note reference.

  93. 93.Titchener, 96.

    Return to note reference.

  94. 94.Titchener, 98.

    Return to note reference.

  95. 95.See Batson, “These Things Called Empathy.”

    Return to note reference.

  96. 96.An argument further developed by Titchener’s student and sometimes collaborator Edwin G. Boring decades later, in 1961. See Boring’s “The Beginning and Growth.” Cf. Canales, Tenth of a Second.

    Return to note reference.

  97. 97.Einfühlung was translated into French in 1869 as sympathie symbolique, suggesting a completely different genealogy than the one I describe here, as well.

    Return to note reference.

  98. 98.Stein, “Radcliffe Manuscripts,” 121, as cited in Meyer, Irresistible Dictation, 211.

    Return to note reference.

  99. 99.On inequalities of race as foundational for psychophysics and early American psychology, see Fretwell, Sensory Experiments.

    Return to note reference.

  100. 100.The idea of a necessary exclusion as essential for the emotional bonding through art is one of the major criticisms leveled by Theodor Adorno against the Wagnerian Gesamtkunstwerk—that aesthetic unity can only occur through the exclusion of the ground through which that unity is produced. See Adorno, In Search of Wagner, 91.

    Return to note reference.

  101. 101.On cultural techniques, see Siegert, Cultural Techniques. What I mean by “materialist” is outlined in Bollmer, Materialist Media Theory. On the technical a priori, see Tuschling, “Historical, Technological and Medial A Priori.”

    Return to note reference.

  102. 102.Spinoza, Ethics, 164.

    Return to note reference.

  103. 103.Spinoza, 180.

    Return to note reference.

  104. 104.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:442–85.

    Return to note reference.

  105. 105.Schopenhauer, Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, 113–258. Schopenhauer’s inclusion here as a predecessor of affect theory is uncommon, and is derived from Fritz Breithaupt’s The Dark Sides of Empathy, which locates Schopenhauer as the first philosopher of empathy. Placing current claims about empathy in the Kantian frame of Schopenhauer should be explored in more depth, especially given how affect and empathy are often assumed opposed to the Kantian critical project and how the “politics” projected onto affect today—along with Schopenhauer’s own ethical arguments—would seem to necessarily be at odds with Schopenhauer’s notorious misogyny and misanthropy. For an example of his misogyny, see Schopenhauer, Parerga and Paralipomena, 2:550–61. For an analysis of Schopenhauer’s misogyny and its relation to will, see Guinness, Schizogenesis, 102–8.

    Return to note reference.

  106. 106.This is one of the main points of critique offered by Ruth Leys in her Ascent of Affect which, she claims, unites contemporary theoretical approaches to affect and the history of American experimental psychology on emotion. Frank and Wilson, in A Silvan Tomkins Handbook, attempt to defend Silvan Tomkins, one of the main psychologists popular among affect theorists in the humanities today, against this charge. I don’t think that they do so successfully, as Tomkins’ model presumes a cybernetic understanding of bodies and behaviors, which also sidelines consciousness and intentionality as epiphenomena.

    Return to note reference.

  107. 107.Kant privileged a third category, the transcendental. But Schopenhauer’s interpretation of Kant invests in the noumenal “will” rather than the phenomenal world of “representation.”

    Return to note reference.

  108. 108.See Brinkema, Forms of the Affects, xii.

    Return to note reference.

  109. 109.This is something of which, I believe, James was quite aware, though many of his followers today seem not to be. Again, to be clear, the targets of my critique are the affect theorists who defer to biology and the brain for their arguments, suggesting that affect is thus “formless” or impossible to qualify, not those who see emotion or sentiment as a political force articulated with a range of other qualities (meaning, form, etc.). This is a notable split that exists with, say, Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, Brian Massumi, Erin Manning, and William Connolly on one side, and Lauren Berlant, Sara Ahmed, and Lawrence Grossberg on the other. The list here is not exhaustive, and some authors tend to bridge these two “camps,” like Steven Shaviro or Mark Hansen, and even others link the affective with the traditions of aesthetic theory, like Fredric Jameson and Sianne Ngai. I’m interested in opposing a neurophysical definition of affect that escapes the symbolic, and thus am referring to the first group of authors I’ve listed here, the many, many scholars who have been influenced by their work, along with the conceptual slippages that happen when the materiality of the body is assumed “affective” and thus beyond language, which is a tendency in affect theory that far exceeds Sedgwick, Massumi, Manning, and Connolly.

    Return to note reference.

  110. 110.Cf. Massumi, Parables for the Virtual.

    Return to note reference.

  111. 111.See Bloor, “The Strengths of the Strong Programme.”

    Return to note reference.

  112. 112.See Vattimo and Rovatti, Weak Thought.

    Return to note reference.

  113. 113.I’m indebted to Maurizio Ferraris’s Documentality and its theorization of “social objects” on this point. For more on my interpretation of Ferraris, and my broader arguments about inscription and documentation, see my Materialist Media Theory, 51–78.

    Return to note reference.

  114. 114.There is a metaphysical assumption here, of course—that the world is material and everything that exists must be grounded in the material. But even then, “matter” is inherently variable, changing, and situated.

    Return to note reference.

  115. 115.Cf. Levinas, Totality and Infinity; Han, Transparency Society.

    Return to note reference.

  116. 116.Leys’s Ascent of Affect has provided the most sustained version of this argument, though she focuses mostly on more recent (or more mainstream) debates than what I emphasize here. For other arguments that share my concerns, see Hemmings, “Invoking Affect,” and Papoulias and Callard, “Biology’s Gift.” An earlier version of my argument can be found in Bollmer, “Pathologies of Affect.”

    Return to note reference.

  117. 117.See, for instance, Scheler’s Nature of Sympathy.

    Return to note reference.

  118. 118.Sedgwick, Touching Feeling, 93.

    Return to note reference.

  119. 119.See Massumi, Parables for the Virtual, 21.

    Return to note reference.

  120. 120.Yaczo, “Fear and Panic,” 377–397.

    Return to note reference.

  121. 121.Otis, Banned Emotions, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  122. 122.On “culture,” see Williams, Culture & Society, xvi.

    Return to note reference.

  123. 123.On making motion into scientific data, see Salazar Sutil, Motion and Representation.

    Return to note reference.

  124. 124.Schmidgen, “Laboratory.”

    Return to note reference.

  125. 125.Shapin, “Invisible Technician,” 556.

    Return to note reference.

  126. 126.Cf. Wershler, Emerson, and Parikka, Lab Book.

    Return to note reference.

  127. 127.Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway; Latour, Science in Action.

    Return to note reference.

  128. 128.Weigel, “Phantom Images,” 33.

    Return to note reference.

  129. 129.Parikka, What Is Media Archaeology?

    Return to note reference.

  130. 130.My approach here shares much with that proposed by Jeremy Packer in “The Conditions of Media’s Possibility.”

    Return to note reference.

  131. 131.Agamben, What Is an Apparatus?, 14

    Return to note reference.

  132. 132.Foucault, Birth of Biopolitics, 32.

    Return to note reference.

  133. 133.See Delaporte, Chagas Disease.

    Return to note reference.

  134. 134.Delaporte, Figures of Medicine, xix.

    Return to note reference.

  135. 135.Feyerabend, Against Method, 7.

    Return to note reference.

  136. 136.Wetherell, Affect and Emotion.

    Return to note reference.

  137. 137.Leys, “Turn to Affect,” 455–58.

    Return to note reference.

  138. 138.Brinkema, Forms of the Affects, xv; Grossberg, Cultural Studies, 192; Bollmer, “Pathologies of Affect,” 303.

    Return to note reference.

  139. 139.Otis, Banned Emotions.

    Return to note reference.

  140. 140.Cf. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §412.

    Return to note reference.

  141. 141.Derrida, Of Grammatology.

    Return to note reference.

  142. 142.This theme appears throughout the work of Erin Manning, including Relationscapes ; Always More Than One ; and The Minor Gesture.

    Return to note reference.

  143. 143.I’m specifically referencing Manning here, who refers to those who are not babies or autistic as “normopaths.” I’d suggest it also informs the work of any affect theorist who draws on Stern’s The Interpersonal World of the Infant, or any theory of affect that draws on (and rejects) Lacanian models of development in order to privilege a form of subjectivity that has not internalized the Symbolic or Imaginary in favor of continual dwelling within the Real. This is, perhaps, a general problem of assuming an ethical or political valiance to the model of subjectivity articulated by Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari in their Capitalism and Schizophrenia books.

    Return to note reference.

  144. 144.I’m again referring to Manning. See Relationscapes, 153–206; Always More Than One, 149–203; Minor Gesture, 111–88.

    Return to note reference.

  145. 145.See Bollmer, Materialist Media Theory, for a more thorough version of this argument. Cf. Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, 39–74.

    Return to note reference.

  146. 146.Siegert, Cultural Techniques.

    Return to note reference.

1. William James’s Planchette

  1. 1.And continue to examine, as they’re still around today. Alicia Puglionesi provides a thorough history of the American Society for Psychical Research in her Common Phantoms, though I feel this book is a bit too presentist in its orientation, claiming that psychical research is an analog of contemporary “citizen science,” which ignores how psychology in James’s day was yet to be a truly empirical science. I do agree with Puglionesi’s attempt to directly place the work of the ASPR as part of the history of American psychology, however.

    Return to note reference.

  2. 2.James, Essays in Psychical Research, 38.

    Return to note reference.

  3. 3.James, “A World of Pure Experience,” 1160.

    Return to note reference.

  4. 4.James, “Confidences of a ‘Psychical Researcher,’” 1250.

    Return to note reference.

  5. 5.Evans, “William James,” 436.

    Return to note reference.

  6. 6.Evans, 435; Cf. James, “On Some Omissions,” 986–1013.

    Return to note reference.

  7. 7.On James’s relation to introspective psychology, see Meyer, Irresistible Dictation, 25. On the rejection of spiritualism by James’s colleagues, there are many examples. For an overview, see Bjork, Compromised Scientist; for a specific discussion of Hugo Münsterberg’s criticisms of James’s spiritualism, see Langdale “S(t)imulation of Mind,” 6.

    Return to note reference.

  8. 8.Meyer, Irresistible Dictation, 26.

    Return to note reference.

  9. 9.James, Essays in Psychical Research, 381.

    Return to note reference.

  10. 10.I’m referring to Titchener, who was based at Cornell, Hugo Münsterberg, whom James would eventually hire to take over and develop his lab at Harvard, and James McKeen Cattell, who would develop experimental psychology at Columbia. See Bjork, Compromised Scientist, 10.

    Return to note reference.

  11. 11.On the ironies of this eventual embrace, see Fretwell, Sensory Experiments, 6–12. James also wrote an enthusiastic introduction to the English translation of Fechner’s Little Book of Life after Death, though it’s clear from this introduction that James admired Fechner’s more “philosophical” aspects than his methodological ones, such as what James called Fechner’s “anti-materialism,” or “the view that the entire material universe, instead of being dead, is inwardly alive and consciously animated” (James, “Introduction,” x). This view that James admires in Fechner has much in common with the materialism of Lucretius and many “new materialisms” today, but this argument is also what guides many of James’s own criticisms of what he calls “materialism” throughout many of his writings.

    Return to note reference.

  12. 12.Bjork, Compromised Scientist, 12.

    Return to note reference.

  13. 13.See Janaway, “Introduction,” xviii.

    Return to note reference.

  14. 14.James, “Confidences of a ‘Psychical Researcher,’” 1261.

    Return to note reference.

  15. 15.James, Essays in Psychical Research, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  16. 16.Quoted in Skrupskelis, “Introduction,” li.

    Return to note reference.

  17. 17.For instance, Davis, High Weirdness, 8, 20–22.

    Return to note reference.

  18. 18.There is significant evidence that James was interested in producing “physical” secular evidence for an afterlife, for instance. See Coon, “Testing the Limits,” 144.

    Return to note reference.

  19. 19.James, Essays in Psychology, 247–48; cf. Barnard, Exploring Unseen Worlds.

    Return to note reference.

  20. 20.This focus on the physicality of the body does seem to vanish in James’s later work as he develops his radical empiricism and levels his criticisms of “medical materialism” in Varieties of Religious Experience, in Writings 1902–1910.

    Return to note reference.

  21. 21.James, Principles of Psychology, 1:5.

    Return to note reference.

  22. 22.Sargent, Planchette, 1–2.

    Return to note reference.

  23. 23.Sargent, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  24. 24.Sargent, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  25. 25.Sargent, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  26. 26.Cf. Peters’s discussion of the links between spiritualism and hermeneutics in Speaking into the Air.

    Return to note reference.

  27. 27.Sargent, Planchette, iv.

    Return to note reference.

  28. 28.Books Sargent wrote after Planchette, such as The Proof Palpable of Immortality and The Scientific Basis of Spiritualism, the latter of which directly engaged with arguments of Wundt, further emphasized his way of linking spiritualism as a “science” at the edges of empirical knowledge, a belief that both he and James shared.

    Return to note reference.

  29. 29.For details and interpretations of James’s depression, see Simon, Genuine Reality, 112–23; Fullinwider, “William James’s ‘Spiritual Crisis’”; or Leary, “New Insights.”

    Return to note reference.

  30. 30.James, Varieties of Religious Experience, 124.

    Return to note reference.

  31. 31.James, 127.

    Return to note reference.

  32. 32.For many of these biographical claims, I’m relying on the “Chronology” published in James, Writings 1902–1910, 1321–49.

    Return to note reference.

  33. 33.Schopenhauer, World as Will and Representation, 1:417; Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, 113–58.

    Return to note reference.

  34. 34.James, Will to Believe, 486.

    Return to note reference.

  35. 35.James, 584.

    Return to note reference.

  36. 36.It’s also clear that James derives some of his claims about emotion from Spinoza, but I think there’s a more solid link between James and Schopenhauer, including a separation between empirical phenomena and a world beyond sensible perception, which is not a claim advanced in Spinoza’s Ethics. The relation between James and Schopenhauer is almost entirely neglected in scholarship on James. In a recent article on James’s “crisis,” David E. Leary states that “no one has ever made much of James’s relation to Schopenhauer or his thought,” and Leary’s work does much to advance the idea that Schopenhauer was, in fact, very significant for James—even though he frames this more in terms of James’s own feelings of depression and stops short of claiming that Schopenhauer had a significant influence on James’s philosophical arguments. See Leary’s “New Insights,” 2.

    Return to note reference.

  37. 37.Schopenhauer, Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, 113–258.

    Return to note reference.

  38. 38.John Durham Peters gets close to acknowledging the link between the two when he argues that several neo-Kantian themes in James’s philosophy, which Kant found unable to be proven but “necessary for a rational and moral life—that nature is governed by law, that the will is free, and that the soul is immortal,” are investigated in both James’s philosophy and his psychical research (Speaking into the Air, 188–89). Lisa Blackman also sees this link in her Immaterial Bodies, and Alicia Puglionesi, in Common Phantoms, acknowledges this intertwining between psychology and psychical research in James, but does so to legitimate psychical research as science. Steven Meyer’s Irresistible Dictation makes similar claims, primarily to describe the relation between James and Gertrude Stein, but Meyer’s work provides a good account of how arguments from more recent authors from the neuropsychological tradition, such as Francisco Varela, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch, assume that James (and even Wundt) relied not on experimental methods but on introspection—a statement that seems to me to excise spiritualistic experimentation (Meyer, Irresistible Dictation, 25). Another notable example would be McGarry, Ghosts of Futures Past, 17–65.

    Return to note reference.

  39. 39.Bjork, Compromised Scientist.

    Return to note reference.

  40. 40.Peters, Speaking into the Air.

    Return to note reference.

  41. 41.Puglionesi, Common Phantoms; Blum, Ghost Hunters.

    Return to note reference.

  42. 42.James, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?,” 1142.

    Return to note reference.

  43. 43.James, 1142.

    Return to note reference.

  44. 44.Brinkema, Forms of the Affects, 8–9.

    Return to note reference.

  45. 45.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:449–50.

    Return to note reference.

  46. 46.Dalgleish, “Emotional Brain,” 583–89.

    Return to note reference.

  47. 47.See Blackman, Immaterial Bodies, 17–18, 30.

    Return to note reference.

  48. 48.James, “What Is an Emotion?,” 188–205. It’s unclear if James had experimented with the planchette by 1884, since there’s no mention of the device in this essay. From his review of Sargent’s Planchette, he was clearly aware of the spiritualist use of planchettes at the time. His own use of the planchette can only be documented as early as 1888, published in 1889 and 1890. His research into hypnotism and other nonconscious states occurred throughout the 1880s, however, and there are many mentions of various spiritualist techniques throughout The Principles of Psychology, including discussions of his experiments with the planchette.

    Return to note reference.

  49. 49.McDermott, “Introduction,” xix.

    Return to note reference.

  50. 50.James, Essays in Psychical Research, 38–39. Interpolation in this quotation is James’s own.

    Return to note reference.

  51. 51.James, 39. This is also recounted in James, Principles of Psychology, 1:208–9.

    Return to note reference.

  52. 52.James, Essays in Psychical Research, 40.

    Return to note reference.

  53. 53.James, 44.

    Return to note reference.

  54. 54.James, 41–42.

    Return to note reference.

  55. 55.James, Essays in Psychology, 254.

    Return to note reference.

  56. 56.James, 259.

    Return to note reference.

  57. 57.James, Essays in Psychical Research, 44.

    Return to note reference.

  58. 58.James, “Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist?,” 1142.

    Return to note reference.

  59. 59.James, 1158.

    Return to note reference.

  60. 60.Erin Manning is the most direct in articulating this kind of argument.

    Return to note reference.

  61. 61.Cf. Bennett, Vibrant Matter.

    Return to note reference.

  62. 62.Cf. Arnold, “Culture and Anarchy”; on the general acceptance of this belief in the “culture and civilization” tradition, along with its links with British history, see Williams, Culture & Society. Note that the German Romantic tradition also shares similar beliefs (albeit ones that did not legitimate imperialism in the same way as the British), embodied in Schiller’s “aesthetic state.” See Schiller, Aesthetic Education; Chytry, Aesthetic State.

    Return to note reference.

  63. 63.Patton, “Planchette,” 4.

    Return to note reference.

  64. 64.Patton, 4.

    Return to note reference.

  65. 65.Pentangelo, “William Fishbough Revealed,” 264.

    Return to note reference.

  66. 66.Wells, Salem Witchcraft. The only signed work reprinted in this book was an article on spiritualism by Harriet Beecher Stowe.

    Return to note reference.

  67. 67.Pentangelo, “William Fishbough Revealed,” 264. Fishbough’s records of Davis were published as Davis’s The Principles of Nature, for which Fishbough served as publisher.

    Return to note reference.

  68. 68.James, Principles of Psychology, 1:163.

    Return to note reference.

  69. 69.James, 182.

    Return to note reference.

  70. 70.James, 284–85.

    Return to note reference.

  71. 71.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:372.

    Return to note reference.

  72. 72.James, 403.

    Return to note reference.

  73. 73.James, Principles of Psychology, 1:105.

    Return to note reference.

  74. 74.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:414–15.

    Return to note reference.

  75. 75.Schopenhauer, Two Fundamental Problems, 224–25. It would be interesting to contrast this understanding of sympathy and sentiment with the version described in Schuller’s Biopolitics of Feeling and Yao’s Disaffected, since Schopenhauer, who is not discussed in either book, is arguing that sympathy is best reserved for those with whom one does not fully identify, even those one is inclined to feel hatred or disgust toward. Central to the arguments of Schuller and Yao is that affective sympathy presumes likeness and similarity and thus enacts violence toward nonnormative, raced, or colonized subjects. James and Schopenhauer suggest a radically different genealogy of sentiment, albeit one also riddled with obvious limitations, such as Schopenhauer’s notorious misogyny.

    Return to note reference.

  76. 76.Schopenhauer, Two Fundamental Problems, 225–26.

    Return to note reference.

  77. 77.James, Principles of Psychology, 1:121.

    Return to note reference.

  78. 78.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:441.

    Return to note reference.

  79. 79.James, 559; also see James, Principles of Psychology, 1:394–96.

    Return to note reference.

  80. 80.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:553.

    Return to note reference.

  81. 81.James, 559.

    Return to note reference.

  82. 82.James, Principles of Psychology, 1:125–26.

    Return to note reference.

  83. 83.A claim that many aesthetic theories, especially those in the Kantian tradition, tend to associate with propaganda and kitsch.

    Return to note reference.

  84. 84.James, Pragmatism, 32.

    Return to note reference.

  85. 85.Peters, Speaking into the Air.

    Return to note reference.

  86. 86.Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria.

    Return to note reference.

  87. 87.Latour, “How to Talk,” 205.

    Return to note reference.

  88. 88.Solomons and Stein, “Normal Motor Automatism,” 492–512.

    Return to note reference.

  89. 89.Given the ongoing “replication crisis” in the experimental sciences, it is amusing to think that James’s “unscientific” work has more validity than many papers published today, given its replication by Solomons and Stein.

    Return to note reference.

  90. 90.Skinner, “Has Gertrude Stein a Secret?,” 50–57.

    Return to note reference.

  91. 91.Meyer’s Irresistible Dictation provides an outstanding overview of the relations between James and Stein (along with other philosophical relations to Stein’s work), along with Stein’s automatic writing experiments. This quote is from his demonstration of why Skinner’s critiques are deeply misguided (224).

    Return to note reference.

  92. 92.Quoted in Skinner, “Has Gertrude Stein a Secret?,” 52.

    Return to note reference.

  93. 93.Skinner, 52–53.

    Return to note reference.

  94. 94.Bjork, Compromised Scientist, 63–64.

    Return to note reference.

2. Books of Faces

  1. 1.Tagg, Burden of Representation, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  2. 2.Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, 13.

    Return to note reference.

  3. 3.Foucault, History of Madness, 44–77.

    Return to note reference.

  4. 4.Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, 13.

    Return to note reference.

  5. 5.Freud was also a student of Charcot at the time, and Freud’s psychoanalysis could be said to be a different “solution” to knowing the pathological states he initially observed at the Salpêtrière. For one approach to the history of psychoanalysis that shares much with what I’m drawing on here, see Davidson, Emergence of Sexuality. Freud is also discussed at length in Kittler’s Discourse Networks.

    Return to note reference.

  6. 6.Quoted in Bunn, Truth Machine, 58.

    Return to note reference.

  7. 7.Carroy and Plas, “Origins of French Experimental Psychology.”

    Return to note reference.

  8. 8.As a point of fact, the British psychiatrist Hugh W. Diamond was the first to use photography in psychiatric practice, predating Duchenne by at least a decade. Diamond’s images did not seem to influence American psychology as I describe it here. For more on Diamond, see Gilman, Face of Madness and Seeing the Insane.

    Return to note reference.

  9. 9.Duchenne de Boulogne, Mécanisme de la physionomie humaine; Bourneville and Régnard, Iconographie photographique de la Salpêtrière.

    Return to note reference.

  10. 10.There are many discussions of the link among photography, death, and ghosts, but a particularly notable one is Batchen’s Burning with Desire, 172–73. On Charcot’s studies of these topics, see Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, 293–301.

    Return to note reference.

  11. 11.Foucault, Birth of Biopolitics, 32–37.

    Return to note reference.

  12. 12.The entire debate surrounding digital photography and digital film as a loss of the indexical is bound up in this assumption. See Doane, “Indexical.”

    Return to note reference.

  13. 13.Tagg, Burden of Representation; cf. Snyder, “Res Ipsa Loquitur.”

    Return to note reference.

  14. 14.Barthes, Camera Lucida, 76–77.

    Return to note reference.

  15. 15.See Tomkins, Affect Imagery Consciousness, 125–33; Ekman, “Duchenne,” 275–79.

    Return to note reference.

  16. 16.More detailed examinations of the photography of Duchenne and Charcot can be found in Delaporte, Anatomy of the Passions, and Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, both of which I’m drawing on for my arguments here.

    Return to note reference.

  17. 17.Duchenne de Boulogne, Mechanism of Human Facial Expression; Delaporte, Anatomy of the Passions.

    Return to note reference.

  18. 18.Darwin, Expression of the Emotions, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  19. 19.This includes sources as diverse as Descartes on the passions and the Sanskrit Nātyashāstra, a text that radically predates European writings about emotion. See Descartes, Passions of the Soul; Dharwadker, “Emotion in Motion.”

    Return to note reference.

  20. 20.Delaporte, Anatomy of the Passions, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  21. 21.Foucault, History of Sexuality, vol. 1; Cf. Davidson, Emergence of Sexuality.

    Return to note reference.

  22. 22.Delaporte, Anatomy of the Passions, 152.

    Return to note reference.

  23. 23.Canguilhem, Normal and the Pathological, 243.

    Return to note reference.

  24. 24.Canguilhem, 243.

    Return to note reference.

  25. 25.Duchenne de Boulogne, Mechanism of Human Facial Expression, 44.

    Return to note reference.

  26. 26.Duchenne de Boulogne, 42–43. See also Sobieszek, Ghost in the Shell, 40–44.

    Return to note reference.

  27. 27.Duchenne de Boulogne, Mechanism of Human Facial Expression, 43.

    Return to note reference.

  28. 28.Sobieszek, Ghost in the Shell, 43

    Return to note reference.

  29. 29.Quoted in Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, 8.

    Return to note reference.

  30. 30.Quoted in Didi-Huberman.

    Return to note reference.

  31. 31.Bourneville and Régnard’s Iconographie, compiled under the supervision of Charcot, was produced between 1875 and 1880. Men did not enter the Salpêtrière until 1881, and only then in an outpatient capacity. While Charcot believed that hysteria was more common in men than most of his contemporaries, there is no photographic evidence of a male hysteric until 1888. See Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, 80.

    Return to note reference.

  32. 32.Didi-Huberman, 30.

    Return to note reference.

  33. 33.Didi-Huberman also notes the importance of seriality for Charcot’s photographs, though he suggests that this seriality narrates or explains the images, which lack meaning when isolated given their “neutrality” when singular (Invention of Hysteria, 85).

    Return to note reference.

  34. 34.Bourneville and Régnard, Iconographie.

    Return to note reference.

  35. 35.Bazin, “Ontology of the Photographic Image,” 8. Cf. Doane, “Indexical”; Barthes, Camera Lucida.

    Return to note reference.

  36. 36.Didi-Huberman, Invention of Hysteria, 87–88.

    Return to note reference.

  37. 37.Didi-Huberman, 87–88.

    Return to note reference.

  38. 38.See Geimer, Inadvertent Images, 174–75. See also Snyder, “Res Ipsa Loquitur.”

    Return to note reference.

  39. 39.Geimer, Inadvertent Images, 143.

    Return to note reference.

  40. 40.Daston and Galison, Objectivity.

    Return to note reference.

  41. 41.Cf. Lessing’s Laocoön. The problem of the medium in the Laocoön was about the impossibility of visually representing in sculpture expressions not previously judged beautiful.

    Return to note reference.

  42. 42.This also relates to how many Americans were interested in expression and embodiment in determining the rhetorical appeal of public speech. See Malin, Feeling Mediated; cf. Scott, Psychology of Public Speaking.

    Return to note reference.

  43. 43.I say “normal” because various personality disorders—specifically, autism, psychopathy, and borderline personality disorder—are all understood today through some breakdown in the cognitive ability to express or judge facial expression. See Bollmer, “Pathologies of Affect.”

    Return to note reference.

  44. 44.Sander, People of the 20th Century.

    Return to note reference.

  45. 45.Benjamin, Selected Writings, 2:510–12.

    Return to note reference.

  46. 46.Benjamin, 695.

    Return to note reference.

  47. 47.Cf. Azoulay, Civil Imagination.

    Return to note reference.

  48. 48.Foucault, Discipline and Punish.

    Return to note reference.

  49. 49.Weigel, “Phantom Images,” 33.

    Return to note reference.

  50. 50.Moors, “Theories of Emotion Causation,” 645.

    Return to note reference.

  51. 51.Fridlund, Human Facial Expression; also see Leys, Ascent of Affect, 252.

    Return to note reference.

  52. 52.Feldman Barrett, How Emotions Are Made. Russell and Feldman Barrett’s theories are contested from a range of perspectives. I would suggest their claims are determined by the techniques they use in their experiments—such as facial electromyography—which would intrinsically lead to a specific definition of an emotion. Ruth Leys critiques both Russell and Feldman Barrett, and goes so far to claim there “is no intellectually viable alternative to Fridlund’s position” (Ascent of Affect, 368).

    Return to note reference.

  53. 53.Leys, Ascent of Affect.

    Return to note reference.

  54. 54.In some of Ekman’s early work, you can find this book as the source for many of his methods, a source that he eventually replaces with self-citations. For an example of Ekman citing the Woodworth Scale for his experiments, see Ekman and Friesen, “Head and Body Cues.”

    Return to note reference.

  55. 55.I’ve mentioned Sylvan Tomkins and Paul Ekman, but this paradigm also includes widely cited figures such as Antonio Damasio, Jaak Panksepp, and Joseph LeDoux.

    Return to note reference.

  56. 56.These editions are as follows: Woodworth, Experimental Psychology; Woodworth and Schlosberg, Experimental Psychology, rev. ed.; and Kling and Riggs, Woodworth & Schlosberg’s Experimental Psychology.

    Return to note reference.

  57. 57.Winston, “Robert Sessions Woodworth,” 391–401.

    Return to note reference.

  58. 58.Admittedly, Tomkins did create the term “affect program,” which means that I’m using this phrase because of my own context of writing. While Tomkins’s work is fascinating and often different from the others I’m mentioning here, especially in Tomkins’s general opposition to the rigid positivism espoused by people like Titchener, his work is probably most important for its synthesis of the model of discrete affects with a cybernetic theory that demonstrates a great deal of continuity between his work and people like Gregory Bateson and Margaret Mead—the latter being Ekman’s main rival in his legitimation of the model of universal basic emotions. See Tomkins, Affect Imagery Consciousness; Leys, Ascent of Affect ; Frank and Wilson, Silvan Tomkins Handbook.

    Return to note reference.

  59. 59.Delaporte, Anatomy of the Passions, 4–5.

    Return to note reference.

  60. 60.Pearl, About Faces, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  61. 61.Lavater, Essays on Physiognomy, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  62. 62.Lavater, 66.

    Return to note reference.

  63. 63.This is central to the history of “empathy.” See Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form, and Space.

    Return to note reference.

  64. 64.For publishing details about the books of these authors—aside from Piderit and Rudolph—see Smith, Charles Darwin, 179–213.

    Return to note reference.

  65. 65.Smith, 216–18.

    Return to note reference.

  66. 66.Lessing, Laocoön.

    Return to note reference.

  67. 67.Darwin, Expression of the Emotions.

    Return to note reference.

  68. 68.There is wide agreement that Darwin’s emotions book must be historically contextualized, but significant disagreement as to why. Jonathan Smith suggests that Darwin be situated in relation to the authors he is drawing on and differentiating himself from. Eric Korn and Paul Ekman argue that Darwin censored himself to avoid offending Victorian Christians. I think Korn and Ekman’s interpretation requires a retrojective projection of Ekman’s arguments into the original text when there’s scant evidence for these claims in the text itself. As well, this interpretation ignores Darwin’s criticism of Piderit, who does make the argument Korn and Ekman attribute to Darwin. Smith, Charles Darwin, 179–80; Korn, “How Far Down,” 23–24.

    Return to note reference.

  69. 69.Darwin, Descent of Man; Fridlund, Human Facial Expression, 14–15.

    Return to note reference.

  70. 70.See Piderit, Mimik und Physiognomik. Darwin’s references to Piderit are rarely discussed in anglophone scholarship except by Fridlund.

    Return to note reference.

  71. 71.Smith, Charles Darwin, 202.

    Return to note reference.

  72. 72.Smith, 208, 221.

    Return to note reference.

  73. 73.Woodworth, Experimental Psychology, 243.

    Return to note reference.

  74. 74.Woodworth, 244.

    Return to note reference.

  75. 75.Piderit, Mimik und Physiognomik, 139–40; Fridlund, Human Facial Expression, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  76. 76.Boring and Titchener, “A Model for the Demonstration of Facial Expression,” 471–85.

    Return to note reference.

  77. 77.As described in their article, this model was initially designed to be a pedagogical tool for classroom demonstrations. As Rand B. Evans has noted, instruments intended for experimental research, for the classroom, and in undergraduate laboratory research, were often very different (“Psychological Instruments,” 322). As well, Boring and Titchener report that the initial model they designed was, in fact, faulty (“Model,” 473). And yet, even with these caveats, this model was used in actual experimental research, reported on in the Woodworth textbook. Even though the model was faulty, even though technologies designed for classroom demonstration were not often intended for laboratory research, Boring and Titchener’s model nonetheless was used in experimental work. This in fact further legitimates my claim that the instrument was deemed faulty in these experiments, if, in this case, for reasons more obvious than problems with the representation of the face.

    Return to note reference.

  78. 78.Woodworth, Experimental Psychology, 247.

    Return to note reference.

  79. 79.Cf. Jarzombek, Psychologizing of Modernity.

    Return to note reference.

  80. 80.Rudolph, Der Ausdruck.

    Return to note reference.

  81. 81.Scott, Psychology of Public Speaking, 101.

    Return to note reference.

  82. 82.While Scott is not discussed in Malin’s Feeling Mediated, this book provides an excellent overview of how perspectives like Scott’s led to the development of public speaking and persuasion in American communication research.

    Return to note reference.

  83. 83.Woodworth, Experimental Psychology, 248.

    Return to note reference.

  84. 84.Ruckmick, “Preliminary Study of the Emotions,” 31. For more on Ruckmick, see Malin, Feeling Mediated, 157–95.

    Return to note reference.

  85. 85.Feleky, “Expression of the Emotions,” 33–41.

    Return to note reference.

  86. 86.Woodworth, Experimental Psychology, 251.

    Return to note reference.

  87. 87.Woodworth and Schlosberg, Experimental Psychology, rev. ed., 118.

    Return to note reference.

  88. 88.Woodworth and Schlosberg, 124.

    Return to note reference.

  89. 89.Taussig, Defacement, 95–97; Guinness, Schizogenesis, 102–9; Schopenhauer, Parerga and Paralipomena, 2:551.

    Return to note reference.

  90. 90.Jones, Sigmund Freud, 2:421; Elms, “Apocryphal Freud.”

    Return to note reference.

  91. 91.Feleky, Feelings and Emotions, n.p.

    Return to note reference.

  92. 92.Feleky’s images are one of the most overt in my story about presuming that aesthetic education can produce liberal sympathy for the marginalized. Cf. Schuller, Biopolitics of Feeling.

    Return to note reference.

  93. 93.Feleky, Feelings and Emotions, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  94. 94.Feleky. All typos in this quotation are from the original.

    Return to note reference.

  95. 95.See Roudinesco, Jacques Lacan & Co., 9.

    Return to note reference.

  96. 96.Fijalkowski, “Question of Play Analysis.”

    Return to note reference.

  97. 97.Frois-Wittmann, “Judgment of Facial Expression,” 116–17.

    Return to note reference.

  98. 98.Frois-Wittmann, 117.

    Return to note reference.

  99. 99.Guinness, Schizogenesis, 104.

    Return to note reference.

  100. 100.Breton, Manifestos of Surrealism, 17; Guinness, Schizogenesis, 109–20.

    Return to note reference.

  101. 101.Frois-Wittmann, “Judgment of Facial Expression,” 134–35. Frois-Wittmann’s own method also deviates from Woodworth—he asked observers to group faces which had, in their minds, similar expressions, though did so without specific categories guiding their groupings. Yet the scale we use today descends from Woodworth, not Frois-Wittmann’s method, thus indicating the importance of negation and not similarity in the judgment of emotion.

    Return to note reference.

  102. 102.Hulin and Katz, “Frois-Wittmann Pictures,” 482–98.

    Return to note reference.

  103. 103.Hulin and Katz, 495.

    Return to note reference.

  104. 104.Engen, Levy, and Schlosberg, “New Series of Facial Expressions,” 264. The experiments performed with the Frois-Wittmann images were repeated with the Lightfoot images in Levy and Schlosberg, “Woodworth Scale,” 121–25.

    Return to note reference.

  105. 105.Kling and Riggs, Woodworth & Schlosberg’s Experimental Psychology.

    Return to note reference.

  106. 106.Leys, Ascent of Affect, 76. For more on Birdwhistell and his relation to film, see Watter, “Scrutinizing.”

    Return to note reference.

  107. 107.Boucher and Ekman, “Replication of Schlosberg’s Evaluation.”

    Return to note reference.

  108. 108.See Frijda, “Recognition of Emotion,” 188.

    Return to note reference.

  109. 109.Leys, Ascent of Affect, 76–128.

    Return to note reference.

  110. 110.Ekman and Friesen, Facial Action Coding System, 6–7.

    Return to note reference.

  111. 111.Frois-Wittmann, “Judgment of Facial Expression,” 117.

    Return to note reference.

  112. 112.Tomkins, “Inverse Archaeology,” 284.

    Return to note reference.

  113. 113.Ekman, Emotions Revealed, 82.

    Return to note reference.

  114. 114.Ekman, 94–95.

    Return to note reference.

  115. 115.Ekman, 96.

    Return to note reference.

3. The Prison Dynograph

  1. 1.In this chapter, I attempt to both link and differentiate psychology and psychiatry, though this points to how the boundaries of the “psy-sciences” are often difficult to define. See Rose, Inventing Our Selves.

    Return to note reference.

  2. 2.Similar arguments to what I advance in this chapter can be found in Schmidgen’s Helmholtz Curves and Canales’s Tenth of a Second. These books are about, respectively, the missing time between a stimulus and response in the firing of a nerve, and the technical standardization of small temporal measurements. Neither of these books discuss Grey Walter and the contingent negative variation, which is essential in linking the measurement of “missing” time and the claims of affect theory that appear derived from James but are, in fact, part of a much broader and more contested field.

    Return to note reference.

  3. 3.Federman, Holmes, and Jacob’s “Deconstructing the Psychopath” provides a critical analysis of psychopathy that shares similar themes as this chapter, but I feel this article begins from assumptions that guide, as this chapter will develop, claims like those of the anti-psychiatrists, rather than explain how this concept was developed with explicit reference to a technical mode of visibility.

    Return to note reference.

  4. 4.The complete and abridged versions of Foucault’s thesis were translated into English as The History of Madness and Madness and Civilization, respectively.

    Return to note reference.

  5. 5.Szasz, Myth of Mental Illness.

    Return to note reference.

  6. 6.Goffman, Asylums.

    Return to note reference.

  7. 7.Cooper, Psychiatry and Anti-psychiatry.

    Return to note reference.

  8. 8.See Kesey, Cuckoo’s Nest; Guattari, I, Little Asylum.

    Return to note reference.

  9. 9.Cooper, Psychiatry and Anti-psychiatry, 24.

    Return to note reference.

  10. 10.Offner, “Electrical Properties of Tissues.”

    Return to note reference.

  11. 11.Weinberg and Dallos, “Franklin F. Offner,” 190–91.

    Return to note reference.

  12. 12.Dondelinger, “Electroencephalographs,” 388–89.

    Return to note reference.

  13. 13.Scott, Understanding EEG, 45–61.

    Return to note reference.

  14. 14.Scott, 191.

    Return to note reference.

  15. 15.Barlow, Electroencephalogram, 3.

    Return to note reference.

  16. 16.Scott, Understanding EEG, 120–121.

    Return to note reference.

  17. 17.Which goes for other forms of brain imagining as well. See Dumit, Picturing Personhood.

    Return to note reference.

  18. 18.EEG wearables are consumer technologies that allow hobbyists and artists to experiment with EEGs at home, usually with the intent of quantifying vital signs or engaging in some of the more questionable aspects of EEGs, like attempts to generate telepathy.

    Return to note reference.

  19. 19.Littlefield, Instrumental Intimacy, 9.

    Return to note reference.

  20. 20.Littlefield, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  21. 21.For an overview of Walter’s EEG work and its relation to cybernetics, see Pickering, Cybernetic Brain, 37–89.

    Return to note reference.

  22. 22.Walter et al., “Contingent Negative Variation.”

    Return to note reference.

  23. 23.Scott, Understanding EEG, 171.

    Return to note reference.

  24. 24.Walter et al., “Contingent Negative Variation,” 382–83.

    Return to note reference.

  25. 25.Walter et al., 382–384.

    Return to note reference.

  26. 26.Scott, Understanding EEG, 171.

    Return to note reference.

  27. 27.Walter et al., “Contingent Negative Variation,” 380. I can find no information about this model of Dynograph. Walter had a Type T Dynograph at hand, though this Type T Dynograph had only eight channels, and the TC, as reported in the article, had sixteen channels.

    Return to note reference.

  28. 28.In this chapter and the next, I use “polygraph” in its popular sense, as a synonym for “lie detector.” In some of the scientific literature from the 1960s, Offner’s technologies are often referred to as polygraphs, though this follows the etymological history of this word as “writing much” or “many writings.” This differentiation is fuzzy, however, since the Dynograph can measure the same things as a lie detector. For an example of Offner’s instruments referred to as “polygraphs,” see Guedry and Collins, Adaptation to Vestibular Disorientation, 1.

    Return to note reference.

  29. 29.For a description of how the polygraph functions, see Baesler, Clearer Than Truth, 23–30.

    Return to note reference.

  30. 30.Bunn, Truth Machine, 147.

    Return to note reference.

  31. 31.Bunn, 141.

    Return to note reference.

  32. 32.Hare, Psychopathy.

    Return to note reference.

  33. 33.See Critchley, “Electrodermal Responses,” for a recent elaboration of the relations between sweating and neurological activity.

    Return to note reference.

  34. 34.For an overview of the problems and potentials of electrodermal measurement in psychology and physiology, see Boucsein et al., “Publication Recommendations.”

    Return to note reference.

  35. 35.Hare and Quinn, “Psychopathy and Autonomic Conditioning,” 223–35.

    Return to note reference.

  36. 36.Hare and Quinn, 225.

    Return to note reference.

  37. 37.Hare and Quinn, 225.

    Return to note reference.

  38. 38.Hare and Quinn, 225.

    Return to note reference.

  39. 39.This version of empathy relates strongly to what is termed “theory of mind,” which suggests that particular personality disorders, including psychopathy and autism, are characterized by an inability to experience “empathy,” defined as the simulation and comprehension of both oneself and others as minded. For a discussion of the “theory of mind” theory and its relation to autism, see Baron-Cohen, Mindblindness.

    Return to note reference.

  40. 40.Hare and Quinn, “Psychopathy and Autonomic Conditioning,” 234.

    Return to note reference.

  41. 41.Baesler, Clearer Than Truth, 26–27.

    Return to note reference.

  42. 42.Hare and Quinn, “Psychopathy and Autonomic Conditioning,” 234.

    Return to note reference.

  43. 43.Kittler, Discourse Networks, 206–25.

    Return to note reference.

  44. 44.Joyce and Baker, “Recalling Psychology’s Past.”

    Return to note reference.

  45. 45.Hare, “Electrodermal and Cardiovascular Correlates,” 122.

    Return to note reference.

  46. 46.Hare, 122.

    Return to note reference.

  47. 47.Leys, “How Did Fear?,” 89.

    Return to note reference.

  48. 48.Schramme, “Introduction,” 17.

    Return to note reference.

  49. 49.Here we can locate Canguilhem’s claims about how the abnormal and pathological precede the normal, and how the pathological is assumed to be a deficiency in some vital capacity of the human body. See his Normal and the Pathological.

    Return to note reference.

  50. 50.Cooper, Psychiatry and Anti-psychiatry, 19; Szasz, Myth of Mental Illness.

    Return to note reference.

  51. 51.Cleckley, Mask of Sanity.

    Return to note reference.

  52. 52.Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 228.

    Return to note reference.

  53. 53.Cooper, “Introduction,” 8.

    Return to note reference.

  54. 54.See Illouz, Cold Intimacies and Saving the Modern Soul.

    Return to note reference.

  55. 55.Westbrook, “‘Enemy of My Enemy.’”

    Return to note reference.

  56. 56.Szasz, Myth of Mental Illness.

    Return to note reference.

  57. 57.Szasz and Freud feature far more prominently in Harrington’s account of this history, in her excellent Mind Fixers, than any other figures mentioned above. To me, this is because Szasz’s arguments were made on grounds that could be easily refuted through medical means. The critiques of Cooper, Laing, Foucault, and Guattari, among others, were far more complex and called for a complete reinvention of society.

    Return to note reference.

  58. 58.Foucault, Abnormal, 57–58. The entire passage where Foucault outlines these three types can be found on pages 44–77.

    Return to note reference.

  59. 59.Hacking, Historical Ontology, 99–114.

    Return to note reference.

  60. 60.James, Principles of Psychology, 2:414–15.

    Return to note reference.

  61. 61.This theme leads to much broader issues related to the history and function of prison. The liberal tradition assumes prison as a space of “reformation,” a theme central to Foucault’s Discipline and Punish. But the pragmatic realities of prison, especially in the United States, rarely if ever follow this “reformist” mission and instead serve to segregate through incarceration, which is often marked by inequalities in race. See Davis, Are Prisons Obsolete?, for an argument about prison abolition in this context.

    Return to note reference.

  62. 62.Knight, “Empathy Circuit.”

    Return to note reference.

  63. 63.Malabou, New Wounded, 3.

    Return to note reference.

  64. 64.Malabou, 50.

    Return to note reference.

  65. 65.Bernhardt and Singer, “Neural Basis of Empathy.”

    Return to note reference.

  66. 66.Blair, Mitchell, and Blair, Psychopath.

    Return to note reference.

  67. 67.For examples that associate autism, psychopathy, and borderline personality disorder through an inability to grasp interpersonal cues, including facial expression, see Baron-Cohen, Science of Evil; Decety and Moriguchi, “Empathic Brain”; Lockwood et al., “Dissecting Empathy”; Dudas et al., “Overlap.”

    Return to note reference.

  68. 68.Psychopathy would be the ability to understand the expressions of others and simulate expressions, but not experience the empathetic mimesis of facial expression; autism is an inability to interpret the expressions of others; borderline personality disorder would be an overreading of facial expressions. These understandings of expression and personality are highly debated, even if they’re very common.

    Return to note reference.

  69. 69.Massumi, Parables for the Virtual.

    Return to note reference.

  70. 70.Among others, see Baron-Cohen, Science of Evil; Fallon, Psychopath Inside ; Kiehl, Psychopath Whisperer. See Stadler, “Empath,” for an analysis of psychopathy and empathy in the television program Hannibal.

    Return to note reference.

  71. 71.Schramme, Being Amoral.

    Return to note reference.

  72. 72.See, for instance, Babiak and Hare, Snakes in Suits.

    Return to note reference.

  73. 73.Seltzer, Serial Killers, 12. See also Seltzer, True Crime.

    Return to note reference.

  74. 74.Cf. Foucault, Discipline and Punish.

    Return to note reference.

  75. 75.Lazzarato, “Immaterial Labor”; Illouz, Cold Intimacies.

    Return to note reference.

  76. 76.Liu, Laws of Cool.

    Return to note reference.

  77. 77.Kotsko, Why We Love Sociopaths; Bollmer, Inhuman Networks, 204–32.

    Return to note reference.

  78. 78.Cf. Seltzer, Serial Killers, 135–40.

    Return to note reference.

  79. 79.Babiak and Hare, Snakes in Suits.

    Return to note reference.

  80. 80.Dutton, Wisdom of Psychopaths.

    Return to note reference.

  81. 81.Adams, Psychopath Factory; Brons, Hegemony of Psychopathy ; Kotsko, Why We Love Sociopaths.

    Return to note reference.

  82. 82.Boltanski and Chiapello, New Spirit of Capitalism; Liu, Laws of Cool.

    Return to note reference.

  83. 83.Cf. Bauman, Liquid Modernity.

    Return to note reference.

  84. 84.Cited in Hare, Without Conscience, 81.

    Return to note reference.

  85. 85.Bollmer, Inhuman Networks.

    Return to note reference.

  86. 86.See Illouz, Cold Intimacies; Liu, Laws of Cool.

    Return to note reference.

  87. 87.Cleckley, Mask of Sanity, 16.

    Return to note reference.

  88. 88.A close reading of Cleckley’s case studies reveals that—at least with some of his patients—his interpretations are clouded by personal biases and judgments. This is obvious in his case study of “Anna,” one of the few women Cleckley discusses.

    Return to note reference.

  89. 89.Baron-Cohen, Science of Evil.

    Return to note reference.

  90. 90.Blair, Mitchell, and Blair, Psychopath, 111–34.

    Return to note reference.

  91. 91.Hare, Without Conscience, 194.

    Return to note reference.

  92. 92.I am reminded of Georges Canguilhem’s comments on how pathology must begin with the patient’s experience of being “unwell,” which is clearly not the case here. The pathology is defined directly through the inability of the patient to consent to the authority of psychological diagnosis. See Normal and the Pathological, 115–23.

    Return to note reference.

  93. 93.Hare, Psychopathy, 8.

    Return to note reference.

  94. 94.Hare and Neumann, “Psychopathy.”

    Return to note reference.

  95. 95.Blair, Mitchell, and Blair, Psychopath, 15.

    Return to note reference.

  96. 96.Davis, Are Prisons Obsolete?

    Return to note reference.

  97. 97.The link between applied psychology and law, in the United States, is indebted to the efforts of Hugo Münsterberg. See Baesler, Clearer Than Truth, 31–65. This association between psychology and the police is regularly discussed, especially in the French context. See Canguilhem, “What Is Psychology?,” especially the final paragraph.

    Return to note reference.

  98. 98.Morris, Wilderness of Error, 31–33, 194–99.

    Return to note reference.

  99. 99.Estelle v. Smith, 451 U.S. 454 (1981), 459–60.

    Return to note reference.

  100. 100.Morris’s 1988 film The Thin Blue Line was initially planned to be a study of James Grigson, and much of this explanation comes from evidence from Morris’s book Wilderness of Error. For another example of Grigson’s significance, see Federman, Holmes, and Jacob, “Deconstructing the Psychopath,” 44–45.

    Return to note reference.

  101. 101.Some of these themes are discussed in Blair, Mitchell, and Blair’s The Psychopath, a book that foregrounds a more directly neuroscientific understanding of psychopathy, if one that correlates neuroscientific evidence with Hare’s checklist. Hare, Black, and Walsh’s “Psychopathy Checklist-Revised” argues that Hare’s checklist is still the standard diagnostic for legal judgment of psychopathy, not other, more technically grounded methods.

    Return to note reference.

  102. 102.See Ronson, Psychopath Test.

    Return to note reference.

  103. 103.Wang, Carceral Capitalism.

    Return to note reference.

  104. 104.Clough, User Unconscious; Hansen, Feed-Forward.

    Return to note reference.

  105. 105.Bollmer, “Pathologies of Affect.”

    Return to note reference.

  106. 106.Cf. Batson, “These Things Called Empathy.”

    Return to note reference.

  107. 107.Cf. Naveh, “Techniques for Emotion Detection”; Bollmer, “Automation of Empathy.”

    Return to note reference.

  108. 108.Aserinsky, “Discovery of REM Sleep,” 216.

    Return to note reference.

4. E-Meter Metaphysics

  1. 1.Daston and Galison, Objectivity, 115–90.

    Return to note reference.

  2. 2.Kittler, Gramophone, Film, Typewriter, 13.

    Return to note reference.

  3. 3.Cf. Kafka, Letters to Milena, 230–31.

    Return to note reference.

  4. 4.Gunn, Modern Occult Rhetoric.

    Return to note reference.

  5. 5.My main sources for arguments about occult philosophy in modern society are Gunn, Modern Occult Rhetoric ; and Eburne, Outsider Theory.

    Return to note reference.

  6. 6.Hubbard, Dianetics, 119.

    Return to note reference.

  7. 7.Cf. Eburne, Outsider Theory, 15–25.

    Return to note reference.

  8. 8.For instance, see memoirs such as Leah Remini and Rebecca Paley’s Troublemaker or Jenna Miscavige Hill and Lisa Pulitzer’s Beyond Belief. Wright’s Going Clear also documents historical instances of this abuse.

    Return to note reference.

  9. 9.See Cowan, “Researching Scientology.”

    Return to note reference.

  10. 10.Westbrook’s Among the Scientologists is, in my opinion, by far the best book on Scientology, though it contains almost no critical engagement with the religion’s history. Urban’s Church of Scientology attempts a “serious, respectful history of the church” (12), one that admits this history but does not disqualify abuse and violence. Most historians of religion seem to approach this abuse as similar to that performed by the Catholic church, or most other religions, both in the present and in history.

    Return to note reference.

  11. 11.For readers interested in Hubbard, most biographical sketches are written by authors hostile to Scientology, using the unsavory details in his personal history to invalidate him and his work. Journalist Lawrence Wright’s Going Clear, while critical, takes a nuanced perspective and contains ample details about Hubbard’s personal life and the religion. Westbrook’s Among the Scientologists barely addresses Hubbard’s biography, as contemporary Scientologists see Hubbard as a flawed figure; his biography is less important to the religion than his methods, which they view less as a matter of faith than as a pragmatic series of techniques for accessing spiritual truth. Other examples of academic research on Scientology worth examining include Urban, Church of Scientology; Lewis, Scientology ; and Lewis and Hellesøy, Handbook of Scientology, among others.

    Return to note reference.

  12. 12.Eburne, Outsider Theory, 358.

    Return to note reference.

  13. 13.Eburne, 358.

    Return to note reference.

  14. 14.Allen, How to Build a Lie.

    Return to note reference.

  15. 15.Quoted in Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 98.

    Return to note reference.

  16. 16.Quoted in Westbrook, 98.

    Return to note reference.

  17. 17.Hubbard, Scientology, 7.

    Return to note reference.

  18. 18.Ekelöf, “Genesis of the Wheatstone Bridge.”

    Return to note reference.

  19. 19.Brain, Pulse of Modernism; Schmidgen, Helmholtz Curves.

    Return to note reference.

  20. 20.For an early description of this process, see Trovillo, “A History of Lie Detection,” 109–10. For a recent description of it, see Baesler, Clearer Than Truth, 23–30.

    Return to note reference.

  21. 21.Eburne, Outsider Theory; Davis, High Weirdness.

    Return to note reference.

  22. 22.Eburne makes this connection explicit in Outsider Theory, 358–59.

    Return to note reference.

  23. 23.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 18.

    Return to note reference.

  24. 24.Wright, Going Clear, 111–12.

    Return to note reference.

  25. 25.Christensen, “Rethinking Scientology,” 63.

    Return to note reference.

  26. 26.Illouz, Saving the Modern Soul.

    Return to note reference.

  27. 27.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 60–63.

    Return to note reference.

  28. 28.Hubbard, Dianetics, 10.

    Return to note reference.

  29. 29.Hubbard, 16, 381–82.

    Return to note reference.

  30. 30.The subtitle of Dianetics was changed after its first edition to The Modern Science of Mental Health.

    Return to note reference.

  31. 31.Whitehead, “Reasonably Fantastic,” 567–73; Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 66.

    Return to note reference.

  32. 32.Westbrook suggests that Dianetics cannot be considered a variation of psychoanalysis because the auditor “does not counsel in the traditional sense of engaging in conversation” (Among the Scientologists, 72). Yet the traditional therapeutic situation in psychoanalysis has the analyst simply listen and take notes. This is overt in some variants, in which the analyst says literally nothing, or where the analysand is prohibited from looking at the analyst.

    Return to note reference.

  33. 33.This end exists in theory, but not in practice—Hubbard would eventually add numerous goals beyond “clear,” advancing along a path Scientology terms “The Bridge to Total Freedom,” which he introduced in 1965, a turn which overtly links Scientology with the occult traditions I’ll discuss later in the chapter. See Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 27–30; Whitehead, “Reasonably Fantastic.”

    Return to note reference.

  34. 34.Freud, “Analysis Terminable and Interminable”; Ferenczi, Final Contributions, 77–86.

    Return to note reference.

  35. 35.Quoted in Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 70.

    Return to note reference.

  36. 36.Hubbard, Dianetics, 87–88.

    Return to note reference.

  37. 37.Hubbard regularly invokes Bergson’s élan vital in the Dianetics books. See Dianetics, 280; and Science of Survival, 3.

    Return to note reference.

  38. 38.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 73.

    Return to note reference.

  39. 39.See Freud, Standard Edition, vol. 1 (1886–1899); Cf. Oliveria et al., “Jean-Martin Charcot’s Influence.”

    Return to note reference.

  40. 40.Harrington, Mind Fixers.

    Return to note reference.

  41. 41.Szasz, Myth of Mental Illness.

    Return to note reference.

  42. 42.Which is notable in and of itself. As Harrington describes in Mind Fixers, the turn to a materialist explanation for mental illness was not just a response to Szasz, but a rejection of Freudianism.

    Return to note reference.

  43. 43.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 66.

    Return to note reference.

  44. 44.Illouz, Saving the Modern Soul, 34.

    Return to note reference.

  45. 45.Leys, Trauma, 83–92.

    Return to note reference.

  46. 46.Illouz, Saving the Modern Soul, 34.

    Return to note reference.

  47. 47.Illouz, 34.

    Return to note reference.

  48. 48.Baesler, Clearer Than Truth, 32–33.

    Return to note reference.

  49. 49.Scott, The Psychology of Public Speaking, 9.

    Return to note reference.

  50. 50.See Moskowitz, “Hugo Münsterberg,” 829.

    Return to note reference.

  51. 51.Woodworth, “Autobiography,” 373–74. Woodworth’s tests would eventually lead to personality testing used to predict future work performance. See Thulin, “First Personality Test.”

    Return to note reference.

  52. 52.Stanger, “Healing the Soldier,” 266–68.

    Return to note reference.

  53. 53.Wright, Going Clear, 26–27.

    Return to note reference.

  54. 54.Quoted in Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 67. Hubbard also mentions this in Science of Survival, 291, 390.

    Return to note reference.

  55. 55.Quoted in Wright, Going Clear, 61.

    Return to note reference.

  56. 56.Stanger, “Healing the Soldier.”

    Return to note reference.

  57. 57.Hubbard, Dianetics, iv.

    Return to note reference.

  58. 58.Hubbard, vii.

    Return to note reference.

  59. 59.Freud, “Note,” 228–29.

    Return to note reference.

  60. 60.Freud, 230.

    Return to note reference.

  61. 61.Freud, Standard Edition, vol. 6; Freud, Interpretation of Dreams.

    Return to note reference.

  62. 62.Racker, Transference and Countertransference.

    Return to note reference.

  63. 63.Carnegie, How to Win Friends. Blum’s Self-Help Compulsion argues that self-help has deep historical precedents, and does so to claim self-help less as a kind of laissez-faire demand of rational self-mastery (as in the case of Carnegie) than as a form of resistant social mobilization.

    Return to note reference.

  64. 64.See, for instance, Carnegie, How to Develop Self-Confidence.

    Return to note reference.

  65. 65.Carnegie, How to Stop Worrying.

    Return to note reference.

  66. 66.Carnegie, xvi. Carnegie repeats this “fact” at least two more times in his book.

    Return to note reference.

  67. 67.Hubbard, Dianetics, iv.

    Return to note reference.

  68. 68.See the discussion of “dub-in” and “demon circuits” in Hubbard, Science of Survival, 77–78, or the broader chapter on “demons” in Hubbard, Dianetics, 103–10.

    Return to note reference.

  69. 69.Hubbard, Dianetics, 106.

    Return to note reference.

  70. 70.Hubbard does say that Dianetics “is not psychoanalysis.” Hubbard, 205.

    Return to note reference.

  71. 71.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 67–73; Urban, Church of Scientology, 36–40.

    Return to note reference.

  72. 72.Freud is mentioned in Science of Survival several times, where Hubbard remarks that the goal of “clear” is “far, far beyond anything envisioned by such investigators as Freud” (18).

    Return to note reference.

  73. 73.Cf. Jay, “History of Alienation.” The reading of Auden here could also be performed through other devotees of psychoanalysis from this period, be they Georges Bataille, Herbert Marcuse, or Wilhelm Reich, the last of whom will be discussed later in the chapter. According to Jay, some of Jacques Lacan’s reinventions of Freud come from his rejection of a Freudian “wholeness” as a goal for psychoanalysis, a theme that directly parallels my use of Auden here.

    Return to note reference.

  74. 74.Auden, Age of Anxiety, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  75. 75.Auden, 55.

    Return to note reference.

  76. 76.Didymus (W. H. Auden), “Sin in the Mirror.”

    Return to note reference.

  77. 77.Illouz, Cold Intimacies, 47.

    Return to note reference.

  78. 78.Jacobs, “Introduction,” xvii–xxi.

    Return to note reference.

  79. 79.Hubbard, Science of Survival, vi–vii.

    Return to note reference.

  80. 80.Cf. Jung, Psychology and the Occult.

    Return to note reference.

  81. 81.Yates, Giordano Bruno and Rosicrucian Enlightenment.

    Return to note reference.

  82. 82.Yates, Giordano Bruno, 4.

    Return to note reference.

  83. 83.Sloterdijk, Critique of Cynical Reason, 128, 130.

    Return to note reference.

  84. 84.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 21.

    Return to note reference.

  85. 85.Westrbrook, 86–91. Also see Hubbard, Scientology. Many popular critics presume that this science fictional aspect of Scientology is “hidden” to outsiders, but this book of Hubbard’s is publicly available. Perhaps more relevant is Westbrook’s finding that practicing Scientologists seem to not believe in this science fictional metaphysics, instead framing it as an excuse to organize the technical practices of Scientology.

    Return to note reference.

  86. 86.Cf. Wright, Going Clear ; Coleman, Hacker, 53–79.

    Return to note reference.

  87. 87.Hubbard, Scientology, 3.

    Return to note reference.

  88. 88.Hubbard, 64.

    Return to note reference.

  89. 89.Hubbard, 79.

    Return to note reference.

  90. 90.A biography of Hubbard that emphasizes his con-artistry is Miller, Bare-Faced Messiah.

    Return to note reference.

  91. 91.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 78. There are other explanations as well, though I feel these assume too much of Hubbard’s ability to simply dupe and con people. Anderson’s “A Brief History of Scientology,” for instance, even suggests that the turn to Scientology was simply because Hubbard was going through a divorce and was “desperately in need of a new project.” This explanation is far too simplistic and does little to work out the similarities and distinctions between Dianetics and Scientology.

    Return to note reference.

  92. 92.Wallis, Road to Total Freedom.

    Return to note reference.

  93. 93.Hubbard, Science of Survival, vi–vii.

    Return to note reference.

  94. 94.Wright, Going Clear, 86

    Return to note reference.

  95. 95.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 80–82.

    Return to note reference.

  96. 96.Westbrook, 196.

    Return to note reference.

  97. 97.Westbrook, 195–99.

    Return to note reference.

  98. 98.Westbrook, 97.

    Return to note reference.

  99. 99.For instance, see Leonard, “Scientology Debunked,” a review of Malko’s Scientology, an early attempt to debunk Hubbard. Kim Cooper’s “Very Different Tonight” also links Reich and Hubbard—along with Crowley.

    Return to note reference.

  100. 100.Eburne, Outsider Theory, 358.

    Return to note reference.

  101. 101.Hubbard also claims Dianetics can potentially cure cancer in Dianetics, 114.

    Return to note reference.

  102. 102.Reich, Ether, God and Devil, 86–87.

    Return to note reference.

  103. 103.Reich, Cancer Biopathy.

    Return to note reference.

  104. 104.Reich, Ether, God and Devil, 112.

    Return to note reference.

  105. 105.These numbers are from the 2015 introduction to Peter Reich’s A Book of Dreams, the memoir of Wilhelm Reich’s son, where Peter is describing the broader context that led to his father’s imprisonment and death.

    Return to note reference.

  106. 106.See Sharaf, Fury on Earth.

    Return to note reference.

  107. 107.For an overview of Palmer’s own beliefs, see The Chiropractor. Palmer’s religious legitimation can be found on pages 1–12 of this book.

    Return to note reference.

  108. 108.Busse, Morgan, and Campbell, “Chiropractic Antivaccination Arguments.”

    Return to note reference.

  109. 109.Kaptchuk and Eisenberg, “Chiropractic.”

    Return to note reference.

  110. 110.Kaptchuk and Eisenberg.

    Return to note reference.

  111. 111.Hubbard, Introducing the E-Meter, 103. This publication presents a pictorial history of all models of the E-Meter. Until 1957, E-Meters were branded as “Mathison Electropsychometers” and relied on vacuum tubes. The E-Meter from 1957, the Hubbard American Blue Meter, was the first “Hubbard Electrometer,” and was the first to use transistors rather than vacuum tubes.

    Return to note reference.

  112. 112.Foucault, Birth of Biopolitics, 27–50.

    Return to note reference.

  113. 113.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 17–18.

    Return to note reference.

  114. 114.Mathison, “Electropsychometer or Bioelectronic Instrument,” 1.

    Return to note reference.

  115. 115.Mathison was following Carl Jung in developing his device. Jung was enthusiastic about the potential of “psycho-galvanometers” in psychoanalytic therapy. See Urban, Church of Scientology, 39.

    Return to note reference.

  116. 116.Mathison, “Electropsychometer or Bioelectronic Instrument,” 1 (emphasis added).

    Return to note reference.

  117. 117.Hubbard, Dianetics, 31.

    Return to note reference.

  118. 118.Hubbard, 31.

    Return to note reference.

  119. 119.Hubbard, Science of Survival, 4.

    Return to note reference.

  120. 120.Tones beyond 4 are not discussed in the text of Science of Survival but are part of the “Hubbard Chart of Human Evaluation and Dianetic Processing,” included with the book and summarizing its arguments.

    Return to note reference.

  121. 121.Hubbard, Dianetics, 280.

    Return to note reference.

  122. 122.Hubbard, 280.

    Return to note reference.

  123. 123.Hubbard, Scientology, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  124. 124.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 82–85.

    Return to note reference.

  125. 125.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 1.

    Return to note reference.

  126. 126.Hubbard, 5.

    Return to note reference.

  127. 127.Hubbard, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  128. 128.Hubbard, 12.

    Return to note reference.

  129. 129.Hubbard, Scientology, 1.

    Return to note reference.

  130. 130.Hubbard, 137–38.

    Return to note reference.

  131. 131.Gunn, Modern Occult Rhetoric, xxiv.

    Return to note reference.

  132. 132.Gunn, 34.

    Return to note reference.

  133. 133.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 69; cf. Wallis, Road to Total Freedom, 111–13; Urban, Church of Scientology, 33–35.

    Return to note reference.

  134. 134.Blum, Self-Help Compulsion.

    Return to note reference.

  135. 135.Gunn, Modern Occult Rhetoric, 93.

    Return to note reference.

  136. 136.Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 31.

    Return to note reference.

  137. 137.Hubbard, “Expanded ARC Straightwire Grade Process Checklist,” “Expanded Grade 0 Process Checklist,” and “Expanded Grade II Process Checklist.”

    Return to note reference.

  138. 138.Hubbard, Introducing the E-Meter, 62.

    Return to note reference.

  139. 139.Hubbard, 63.

    Return to note reference.

  140. 140.Hubbard, 64.

    Return to note reference.

  141. 141.Hubbard, 65.

    Return to note reference.

  142. 142.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 17.

    Return to note reference.

  143. 143.Hubbard, Introducing the E-Meter, 66.

    Return to note reference.

  144. 144.Hubbard, 67.

    Return to note reference.

  145. 145.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 21.

    Return to note reference.

  146. 146.Hubbard, Introducing the E-Meter, 68.

    Return to note reference.

  147. 147.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 25.

    Return to note reference.

  148. 148.Hubbard, 25.

    Return to note reference.

  149. 149.Hubbard, 26.

    Return to note reference.

  150. 150.Hubbard, Introducing the E-Meter, 69.

    Return to note reference.

  151. 151.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 27.

    Return to note reference.

  152. 152.See Wright, Going Clear, 122–23.

    Return to note reference.

  153. 153.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 125.

    Return to note reference.

  154. 154.Hubbard, Introducing the E-Meter, 70.

    Return to note reference.

  155. 155.Hubbard, 71.

    Return to note reference.

  156. 156.Hubbard, 72.

    Return to note reference.

  157. 157.Hubbard, 73.

    Return to note reference.

  158. 158.Scientology treats this as a technical term. See Westbrook, Among the Scientologists, 108–9.

    Return to note reference.

  159. 159.Hubbard, E-Meter Essentials, 41–42.

    Return to note reference.

  160. 160.Hubbard, Scientology, 113.

    Return to note reference.

  161. 161.Hubbard, 114.

    Return to note reference.

  162. 162.Hubbard, Book of E-Meter Drills, 11.

    Return to note reference.

  163. 163.Hubbard, 84.

    Return to note reference.

  164. 164.Gunn, Modern Occult Rhetoric, 169–71.

    Return to note reference.

  165. 165.Compare this to the descriptions of Robert Hare’s psychopathy checklist (or PCL-R) when used in legal and carceral settings, in Hare, Black, and Walsh, “Psychopathy Checklist-Revised,” 251.

    Return to note reference.

  166. 166.Barbrook and Cameron, “Californian Ideology,” 44–45.

    Return to note reference.

  167. 167.Elaborations and extensions of this argument can be found in Turner, From Counterculture to Cyberculture and Davis, High Weirdness.

    Return to note reference.

  168. 168.Cf. Boltanski and Chiapello, New Spirit of Capitalism.

    Return to note reference.

  169. 169.Bollmer, Inhuman Networks.

    Return to note reference.

  170. 170.Illouz, Cold Intimacies and Saving the Modern Soul.

    Return to note reference.

  171. 171.Lazzarato, “Immaterial Labor”; Bauman, Liquid Modernity.

    Return to note reference.

Conclusion

  1. 1.Canguilhem, “What is Psychology?,” 200.

    Return to note reference.

  2. 2.Canguilhem, 212.

    Return to note reference.

  3. 3.Cendrars, Moravagine, 26–27.

    Return to note reference.

  4. 4.Cf. Brinkema, Forms of the Affects, xiv–xvi. On media as portals, see Cubitt, “Limen, Portal, Network Subjectivities.”

    Return to note reference.

  5. 5.Otherwise, we would drift into the theology of Scientology.

    Return to note reference.

  6. 6.Massumi, Parables for the Virtual, 20.

    Return to note reference.

  7. 7.See Sorell, Scientism.

    Return to note reference.

  8. 8.Cf. Yates, Rosicrucian Enlightenment.

    Return to note reference.

  9. 9.Brinkema, Forms of the Affects, xvi.

    Return to note reference.

  10. 10.While Tony Sampson and Mark Hansen do not make this argument, their version of affect theory seems, to me, to be closest to this view. Eugenie Brinkema I also believe to be doing something similar, and, as I see it, it would be relatively easy to also read Sianne Ngai, Marie-Louise Angerer, and possibly even Steven Shaviro as making similar claims.

    Return to note reference.

  11. 11.Bachelard, New Scientific Spirit, 13.

    Return to note reference.

  12. 12.Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway, 56.

    Return to note reference.

  13. 13.Delaporte, Chagas Disease; Feyerabend, Against Method.

    Return to note reference.

  14. 14.Brennan, Transmission of Affect, 7.

    Return to note reference.

  15. 15.Prinz, “Against Empathy,” 214.

    Return to note reference.

  16. 16.Cf. Breithaupt, Dark Sides of Empathy, which argues that this social violence is a result of cognitive empathy.

    Return to note reference.

  17. 17.Hogan, Literature and Emotion, 20. See also Gallese and Guerra, Empathic Screen.

    Return to note reference.

  18. 18.See Schuller, Biopolitics of Feeling.

    Return to note reference.

  19. 19.Levinas, Totality and Infinity.

    Return to note reference.

  20. 20.Han, Transparency Society, 2.

    Return to note reference.

  21. 21.Cf. Guinness, “Coloniser and Corpus Nullius.”

    Return to note reference.

  22. 22.See Bollmer, “Empathy Machines”; Bollmer, “From Immersion to Empathy”; and Bollmer and Guinness, “Empathy and Nausea.”

    Return to note reference.

Annotate

Next Chapter
BIBLIOGRAPHY
PreviousNext
Open access edition funded by the National Endowment for the Humanities

Portions of the Introduction and chapter 2 were originally published in a different form in “Books of Faces: Cultural Techniques of Basic Emotions,” NECSUS: European Journal of Media Studies 8, no. 1 (2019): 125–50; the original article was published under a CC-BY-4.0 Creative Commons license.

Copyright 2023 by the Regents of the University of Minnesota

The Affect Lab: The History and Limits of Measuring Emotion is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0).
Powered by Manifold Scholarship. Learn more at
Opens in new tab or windowmanifoldapp.org